4
Introduction Regular expressions are one of the most ubiquitous formalisms of theoretical computer science. Commonly, they are understood in terms of their denotational semantics, that is, through formal languages — the regular languages. This view is inductive in nature: two primitives are equivalent if they are constructed in the same way. Alternatively, regular expressions can be understood in terms of their operational semantics, that is, through finite automata. This view is coinductive in nature: two primitives are equivalent if they are deconstructed in the same way. It is implied by Kleene’s famous theorem that both views are equivalent: regular languages are precisely the formal languages accepted by finite automata. In this blogpost, we utilise Dafny’s built-in inductive and coinductive reasoning capabilities to show that the two semantics of regular expressions are well-behaved, in the sense they are in fact one and the same, up to pointwise bisimulation. Denotational Semantics In this section, we define regular expressions and formal languages, introduce the concept of bisimilarity, formalise the denotational semantics of regular expressions as a function from regular expressions to formal languages, and prove that the latter is an algebra homomorphism. Regular Expressions as Datatype We define the set of regular expressions parametric in an alphabet A as an inductive datatype: datatype Exp = Zero | One | Char(A) | Plus(Exp, Exp) | Comp(Exp, Exp) | Star(Exp) Note that above, and later, we make use of Dafny's type parameter completion. The definition captures that a regular expression is either a primitive character Char(a), a non-deterministic choice between two regular expressions Plus(e1, e2), a sequential composition of two regular expressions Comp(e1, e2), a finite number of self-iterations Star(e), or one of the constants Zero (the unit of Plus) and One (the unit of Comp). At a higher level, the above defines Exp as the smallest algebraic structure that is equipped with two constants, contains all elements of type A, and is closed under two binary operations and one unary operation. Formal Languages as Codatatype We define the set of formal languages parametric in an alphabet A as a coinductive codatatype: codatatype Lang = Alpha(eps: bool, delta: A -> Lang) Note that we used the type-parameter mode !, which indicates that there could be strictly more values of type Lang than values of type A, for any type A, and that there is no subtype relation between Lang and Lang, for any two types A, B. A more detailed explanation of the topic can be found here. To some, the choice above might seem odd at first sight. If you are familiar with the topic, you likely have expected a formal language to be defined more concretely as a set of finite sequences (sometimes called words), iset>. Rest assured, we agree — up to an appropriate notion of equality! Whereas you characterise languages intrinsically, we treat them extrinsically, in terms of their universal property: it is well known that iset> forms the greatest coalgebraic structure (think of a deterministic automaton without initial state) S that is equipped with functions eps: S -> bool and delta: S → (A → S). Indeed, for any set U of finite sequences, we can verify whether U contains the empty sequence, U.eps == ([] in U), and for any a: A, we can transition to the set U.delta(a) == (iset s | [a] + s in U). Here, we choose the more abstract perspective on formal languages as it hides irrelevant specifics and thus allows us to write more elegant proofs. An Algebra of Formal Languages If you think of formal languages as the set of all sets of finite sequences, you will soon realise that languages admit quite a bit of algebraic structure. For example, there exist two languages of distinct importance (can you already guess which ones?), and one can obtain a new language by taking e.g. the union of two languages. In fact, if you think about it for a bit longer, you’ll realise that formal languages admit exactly the same type of algebraic structure as the one you’ve encountered when we defined regular expressions! First, there exists the empty language Zero() that contains no words at all. Under the view above, we find Zero().eps == false and Zero().delta(a) == Zero(), since the empty set does not contain the empty sequence, and the derivative iset s | [a] + s in iset{} with respect to any a: A yields again the empty set, respectively. We thus define: function Zero(): Lang { Alpha(false, (a: A) => Zero()) } Using similar reasoning, we additionally derive the following definitions. In order, we formalise i) the language One() that contains only the empty sequence; ii) for any a: A the language Singleton(a) that consists of only the word [a]; iii) the language Plus(L1, L2) which consists of the union of the languages L1 and L2; iv) the language Comp(L1, L2) that consists of all possible concatenation of words in L1 and L2; and v) the language Star(L) that consists of all finite compositions of L with itself. Our definitions match what is well-known as Brzozowski derivatives. function One(): Lang { Alpha(true, (a: A) => Zero()) } function Singleton(a: A): Lang { Alpha(false, (b: A) => if a == b then One() else Zero()) } function {:abstemious} Plus(L1: Lang, L2: Lang): Lang { Alpha(L1.eps || L2.eps, (a: A) => Plus(L1.delta(a), L2.delta(a))) } function {:abstemious} Comp(L1: Lang, L2: Lang): Lang { Alpha( L1.eps && L2.eps, (a: A) => Plus(Comp(L1.delta(a), L2), Comp(if L1.eps then One() else Zero(), L2.delta(a))) ) } function Star(L: Lang): Lang { Alpha(true, (a: A) => Comp(L.delta(a), Star(L))) } Note that the {:abstemious} attribute above signals that a function does not need to unfold a codatatype instance very far (perhaps just one destructor call) to prove a relevant property. Knowing this is the case can aid the proofs of properties about the function. In this case, it is needed to convince Dafny that the corecursive calls in Comp and Star are logically consistent. Denotational Semantics as Induced Morphism The denotational semantics of regular expressions can now be defined through induction, as a function Denotational: Exp -> Lang, by making use of the operations on languages we have just defined: function Denotational(e: Exp): Lang { match e case Zero => Languages1.Zero() case One => Languages2.One() case Char(a) => Languages2.Singleton(a) case Plus(e1, e2) => Languages2.Plus(Denotational(e1), Denotational(e2)) case Comp(e1, e2) => Languages2.Comp(Denotational(e1), Denotational(e2)) case Star(e1) => Languages2.Star(Denotational(e1)) }Bisimilarity and Coinduction Let us briefly introduce a notion of equality between formal languages that will be useful soon. A binary relation R between languages is called a bisimulation, if for any two languages L1, L2 related by R the following holds: i) L1 contains the empty word iff L2 does; and ii) for any a: A, the derivatives L1.delta(a) and L2.delta(a) are again related by R. As it turns out, the union of two bisimulations is again a bisimulation. In consequence, one can combine all possible bisimulations into a single relation: the greatest bisimulation. In Dafny, we can formalise the latter as a greatest predicate: greatest predicate Bisimilar[nat](L1: Lang, L2: Lang) { && (L1.eps == L2.eps) && (forall a :: Bisimilar(L1.delta(a), L2.delta(a))) } It is instructive to think of a greatest predicate as pure syntactic sugar. Indeed, under the hood, Dafny’s compiler uses the body above to implicitly generate i) for any k: nat, a prefix predicate Bisimilar#[k](L1, L2) that signifies that the languages L1 and L2 concur on the first k-unrollings of the definition above; and ii) a predicate Bisimilar(L1, L2) that is true iff Bisimilar#[k](L1, L2) is true for all k: nat: /* Pseudo code for illustration purposes */ predicate Bisimilar(L1: Lang, L2: Lang) { forall k: nat :: Bisimilar#[k](L1, L2) } predicate Bisimilar#[k: nat](L1: Lang, L2: Lang) decreases k { if k == 0 then true else && (L1.eps == L2.eps) && (forall a :: Bisimilar#[k-1](L1.delta(a), L2.delta(a))) } Now that we have its definition in place, let us establish a property about bisimilarity, say, that it is a reflexive relation. With the greatest lemma construct, Dafny is able to able to derive a proof completely on its own: greatest lemma BisimilarityIsReflexive[nat](L: Lang) ensures Bisimilar(L, L) {} Once again, it is instructive to think of a greatest lemma as pure syntactic sugar. Under the hood, Dafny’s compiler uses the body of the greatest lemma to generate i) for any k: nat, a prefix lemma BisimilarityIsReflexive#[k](L) that ensures the prefix predicate Bisimilar#[k](L, L); and ii) a lemma BisimilarityIsReflexive(L) that ensures Bisimilar(L, L) by calling Bisimilar#[k](L, L) for all k: nat: /* Pseudo code for illustration purposes */ lemma BisimilarityIsReflexive(L: Lang) ensures Bisimilar(L, L) { forall k: nat ensures Bisimilar#[k](L, L) { BisimilarityIsReflexive#[k](L); } } lemma BisimilarityIsReflexive#[k: nat](L: Lang) ensures Bisimilar#[k](L, L) decreases k { if k == 0 { } else { forall a ensures Bisimilar#[k-1](L.delta(a), L.delta(a)) { BisimilarityIsReflexive#[k-1](L.delta(a)); } } } If you are interested in the full details, we recommend taking a look at this note on coinduction, predicates, and ordinals. Denotational Semantics as Algebra Homomorphism For a moment, consider the function var f: nat -> nat := (n: nat) => n + n which maps a natural number to twice its value. The function f is structure-preserving: for any m: nat we have f(m * n) == m * f(n), i.e. f commutes with the (left-)multiplication of naturals. In this section, we are interested in functions of type f: Exp -> Lang (more precisely, in Denotational: Exp -> Lang) that commute with the algebraic structures we encountered in Regular Expressions as Datatype and An Algebra of Formal Languages, respectively. We call such structure-preserving functions algebra homomorphisms. To define pointwise commutativity in this context, we’ll have to be able to compare languages for equality. As you probably guessed, bisimilarity will do the job: ghost predicate IsAlgebraHomomorphism(f: Exp -> Lang) { forall e :: IsAlgebraHomomorphismPointwise(f, e) } ghost predicate IsAlgebraHomomorphismPointwise(f: Exp -> Lang, e: Exp) { Bisimilar( f(e), match e case Zero => Languages1.Zero() case One => Languages2.One() case Char(a) => Languages2.Singleton(a) case Plus(e1, e2) => Languages2.Plus(f(e1), f(e2)) case Comp(e1, e2) => Languages2.Comp(f(e1), f(e2)) case Star(e1) => Languages2.Star(f(e1)) ) } Note that we used the ghost modifier (which signals that an entity is meant for specification only, not for compilation). A greatest predicate is always ghost, so IsAlgebraHomomorphismPointwise must be declared ghost to call Bisimilar, and IsAlgebraHomomorphism must be declared ghost to call IsAlgebraHomomorphismPointwise. The proof that Denotational is an algebra homomorphism is straightforward: it essentially follows from bisimilarity being reflexive: lemma DenotationalIsAlgebraHomomorphism() ensures IsAlgebraHomomorphism(Denotational) { forall e ensures IsAlgebraHomomorphismPointwise(Denotational, e) { BisimilarityIsReflexive(Denotational(e)); } }Operational Semantics In this section, we provide an alternative perspective on the semantics of regular expressions. We equip the set of regular expressions with a coalgebraic structure, formalise its operational semantics as a function from regular expressions to formal languages, and prove that the latter is a coalgebra homomorphism. A Coalgebra of Regular Expressions In An Algebra of Formal Languages we equipped the set of formal languages with an algebraic structure that resembles the one of regular expressions. Now, we are aiming for the reverse: we would like to equip the set of regular expressions with a coalgebraic structure that resembles the one of formal languages. More concretely, we would like to turn the set of regular expressions into a deterministic automaton (without initial state) in which a state e is i) accepting iff Eps(e) == true and ii) transitions to a state Delta(e)(a) if given the input a: A. Note how our definitions resemble the Brzozowski derivatives we previously encountered: function Eps(e: Exp): bool { match e case Zero => false case One => true case Char(a) => false case Plus(e1, e2) => Eps(e1) || Eps(e2) case Comp(e1, e2) => Eps(e1) && Eps(e2) case Star(e1) => true } function Delta(e: Exp): A -> Exp { (a: A) => match e case Zero => Zero case One => Zero case Char(b) => if a == b then One else Zero case Plus(e1, e2) => Plus(Delta(e1)(a), Delta(e2)(a)) case Comp(e1, e2) => Plus(Comp(Delta(e1)(a), e2), Comp(if Eps(e1) then One else Zero, Delta(e2)(a))) case Star(e1) => Comp(Delta(e1)(a), Star(e1)) }Operational Semantics as Induced Morphism The operational semantics of regular expressions can now be defined via coinduction, as a function Operational: Exp -> Lang, by making use of the coalgebraic structure on expressions we have just defined: function Operational(e: Exp): Lang { Alpha(Eps(e), (a: A) => Operational(Delta(e)(a))) }Operational Semantics as Coalgebra Homomorphism In Denotational Semantics as Algebra Homomorphism we defined algebra homomorphisms as functions f: Exp -> Lang that commute with the algebraic structures of regular expressions and formal languages, respectively. Analogously, let us now call a function of the same type a coalgebra homomorphism, if it commutes with the coalgebraic structures of regular expressions and formal languages, respectively: ghost predicate IsCoalgebraHomomorphism(f: Exp -> Lang) { && (forall e :: f(e).eps == Eps(e)) && (forall e, a :: Bisimilar(f(e).delta(a), f(Delta(e)(a)))) } It is straightforward to prove that Operational is a coalgebra homomorphism: once again, the central argument is that bisimilarity is a reflexive relation. lemma OperationalIsCoalgebraHomomorphism() ensures IsCoalgebraHomomorphism(Operational) { forall e, a ensures Bisimilar(Operational(e).delta(a), Operational(Delta(e)(a))) { BisimilarityIsReflexive(Operational(e).delta(a)); } }Well-Behaved Semantics So far, we have seen two dual approaches for assigning a formal language semantics to regular expressions: Denotational: an algebra homomorphism obtained via induction Operational: a coalgebra homomorphism obtained via coinduction Next, we show that the denotational and operational semantics of regular expressions are well-behaved: they constitute two sides of the same coin. First, we show that Denotational is also a coalgebra homomorphism, and that coalgebra homomorphisms are unique up to bisimulation. We then deduce from the former that Denotational and Operational coincide pointwise, up to bisimulation. Finally, we show that Operational is also an algebra homomorphism. Denotational Semantics as Coalgebra Homomorphism In this section, we establish that Denotational not only commutes with the algebraic structures of regular expressions and formal languages, but also with their coalgebraic structures: lemma DenotationalIsCoalgebraHomomorphism() ensures IsCoalgebraHomomorphism(Denotational) The proof of the lemma is a bit more elaborate than the ones we have encountered so far. It can be divided into two subproofs, both of which make use of induction. One of the subproofs is straightforward, the other, more difficult one, again uses the reflexivity of bisimilarity, but also that the latter is a congruence relation with respect to Plus and Comp: greatest lemma PlusCongruence[nat](L1a: Lang, L1b: Lang, L2a: Lang, L2b: Lang) requires Bisimilar(L1a, L1b) requires Bisimilar(L2a, L2b) ensures Bisimilar(Plus(L1a, L2a), Plus(L1b, L2b)) {} lemma CompCongruence(L1a: Lang, L1b: Lang, L2a: Lang, L2b: Lang) requires Bisimilar(L1a, L1b) requires Bisimilar(L2a, L2b) ensures Bisimilar(Comp(L1a, L2a), Comp(L1b, L2b)) Dafny is able to prove PlusCongruence on its own, as it can take advantage of the syntactic sugaring of the greatest lemma construct. For CompCongruence we have to put in a bit of manual work ourselves. Coalgebra Homomorphisms Are Unique The aim of this section is to show that, up to pointwise bisimilarity, there only exists one coalgebra homomorphism of type Exp -> Lang: lemma UniqueCoalgebraHomomorphism(f: Exp -> Lang, g: Exp -> Lang, e: Exp) requires IsCoalgebraHomomorphism(f) requires IsCoalgebraHomomorphism(g) ensures Bisimilar(f(e), g(e)) As is well-known, the statement may in fact be strengthened to: for any coalgebra C there exists exactly one coalgebra homomorphism of type C -> Lang , up to pointwise bisimulation. For our purposes, the weaker statement above will be sufficient. At the heart of the proof lies the observation that bisimilarity is transitive: greatest lemma BisimilarityIsTransitive[nat](L1: Lang, L2: Lang, L3: Lang) requires Bisimilar(L1, L2) && Bisimilar(L2, L3) ensures Bisimilar(L1, L3) {} In fact, in practice, we actually use a slightly more fine grained formalisation of transitivity, as is illustrated below by the proof of UniqueCoalgebraHomomorphismHelperPointwise, which is used in the proof of UniqueCoalgebraHomomorphism: lemma UniqueCoalgebraHomomorphismHelperPointwise(k: nat, f: Exp -> Lang, g: Exp -> Lang, L1: Lang, L2: Lang) requires IsCoalgebraHomomorphism(f) requires IsCoalgebraHomomorphism(g) requires exists e :: Bisimilar#[k](L1, f(e)) && Bisimilar#[k](L2, g(e)) ensures Bisimilar#[k](L1, L2) { var e :| Bisimilar#[k](L1, f(e)) && Bisimilar#[k](L2, g(e)); if k != 0 { forall a ensures Bisimilar#[k-1](L1.delta(a), L2.delta(a)) { BisimilarityIsTransitivePointwise(k-1, L1.delta(a), f(e).delta(a), f(Delta(e)(a))); BisimilarityIsTransitivePointwise(k-1, L2.delta(a), g(e).delta(a), g(Delta(e)(a))); UniqueCoalgebraHomomorphismHelperPointwise(k-1, f, g, L1.delta(a), L2.delta(a)); } } } lemma BisimilarityIsTransitivePointwise(k: nat, L1: Lang, L2: Lang, L3: Lang) ensures Bisimilar#[k](L1, L2) && Bisimilar#[k](L2, L3) ==> Bisimilar#[k](L1, L3) { if k != 0 { if Bisimilar#[k](L1, L2) && Bisimilar#[k](L2, L3) { assert Bisimilar#[k](L1, L3) by { forall a ensures Bisimilar#[k-1](L1.delta(a), L3.delta(a)) { BisimilarityIsTransitivePointwise(k-1, L1.delta(a), L2.delta(a), L3.delta(a)); } } } } }Denotational and Operational Semantics Are Bisimilar We are done! From the previous results, we can immediately deduce that denotational and operational semantics are the same, up to pointwise bisimilarity: lemma OperationalAndDenotationalAreBisimilar(e: Exp) ensures Bisimilar(Operational(e), Denotational(e)) { OperationalIsCoalgebraHomomorphism(); DenotationalIsCoalgebraHomomorphism(); UniqueCoalgebraHomomorphism(Operational, Denotational, e); }Operational Semantics as Algebra Homomorphism As a bonus, for the sake of symmetry, let us also prove that Operational is an algebra homomorphism. (We already know that it is a coalgebra homomorphism, and that Denotational is both an algebra and coalgebra homomorphism.) lemma OperationalIsAlgebraHomomorphism() ensures IsAlgebraHomomorphism(Operational) The idea of the proof is to take advantage of Denotational being an algebra homomorphism, by translating its properties to Operational via the lemma in Denotational and Operational Semantics Are Bisimilar. The relevant new statements capture that bisimilarity is symmetric and a congruence with respect to the Star operation: greatest lemma BisimilarityIsSymmetric[nat](L1: Lang, L2: Lang) ensures Bisimilar(L1, L2) ==> Bisimilar(L2, L1) ensures Bisimilar(L1, L2) <== Bisimilar(L2, L1) {} lemma StarCongruence(L1: Lang, L2: Lang) requires Bisimilar(L1, L2) ensures Bisimilar(Star(L1), Star(L2))Conclusion We have used Dafny’s built-in inductive and coinductive reasoning capabilities to define two language semantics for regular expressions: denotational and operational semantics. Through a number of dualities — construction and deconstruction, algebras and coalgebras, and congruence and bisimilarity — we have proven the semantics to be two sides of the same coin. The blogpost is inspired by research in the field of Coalgebra, which was pioneered by Rutten, Gumm, and others. The concept of well-behaved semantics goes back to Turi and Plotkin and was adapted by Jacobs to the case of regular expressions. We heavily used automata theoretic constructions from the 1960s, originally investigated by Brzozowski (a more modern presentation can be found e.g. here). Our presentation focused on the most important intuitive aspects of the proofs. To dive deep, please take a look at the full Dafny source code, which is available here, here, and here.
You must log in or # to comment.